On Cantor's First Uncountability Proof, Pick's Theorem, and the Irrationality of the Golden Ratio

نویسندگان

  • Mike Krebs
  • Thomas Wright
چکیده

In Cantor’s original proof of the uncountability of the reals (not the diagonalization argument), he constructs, given any countable sequence of real numbers, a real number not in the sequence. When we apply this argument to a certain standard enumeration of the rationals, the real number we produce will necessarily be irrational. Using some planar geometry, including Pick’s theorem on the number of lattice points enclosed within certain polygonal regions, we show that this number is the reciprocal of the Golden Ratio, whence follows the well-known fact that the Golden Ratio is irrational. In 1874, two years before the publication of his famous diagonalization argument, Georg Cantor’s first proof of the uncountability of the real numbers appeared in print [1]. Surprisingly, a small twist on Cantor’s line of reasoning shows that the Golden Ratio is irrational, as we shall demonstrate herewith. En route, we will make use of another classic 19th century theorem by another Georg, this time Georg Pick. Pick’s Theorem [2] provides a simple formula for the number of lattice points enclosed within a simply connected polygonal region in the plane with lattice point vertices. We begin by recapitulating Cantor’s 1874 proof. To show that the real numbers are uncountable, we must show that given any countable sequence of distinct real numbers, there exists another real number not in the sequence. Like the diagonalization argument, we will do so by providing an explicit alogrithm which produces such a number; unlike the diagonalization argument, we will employ not decimal expansions but order properties of the real numbers. Let (an) be a countable sequence of distinct real numbers. Suppose that there are two distinct terms aj and ak such that no term a` lies strictly between aj and ak—in other words, suppose that {an} does not possess the Intermediate Value Property. Let L be any real number strictly between aj and ak, for example aj + ak 2 . Then L is not in the sequence (an). Now suppose that (an) does have the Intermediate Value Property. Cantor recursively constructs two new sequences (bn) and (cn) as follows. Let b1 = a1, and let c1 = a2. Let bk+1 be the first term in (an) that lies strictly between bk and ck. Let ck+1 be the first term in (an) that lies strictly between bk+1 and ck.

برای دانلود متن کامل این مقاله و بیش از 32 میلیون مقاله دیگر ابتدا ثبت نام کنید

ثبت نام

اگر عضو سایت هستید لطفا وارد حساب کاربری خود شوید

منابع مشابه

Diagonal arguments and fixed points

‎A universal schema for diagonalization was popularized by N.S‎. ‎Yanofsky (2003)‎, ‎based on a pioneering work of F.W‎. ‎Lawvere (1969)‎, ‎in which the existence of a (diagonolized-out and contradictory) object implies the existence of a fixed-point for a certain function‎. ‎It was shown that many self-referential paradoxes and diagonally proved theorems can fit in that schema‎. ‎Here‎, ‎we fi...

متن کامل

On the Closed-Form Solution of a Nonlinear Difference Equation and Another Proof to Sroysang’s Conjecture

The purpose of this paper is twofold. First we derive theoretically, using appropriate transformation on x(n), the closed-form solution of the nonlinear difference equation x(n+1) = 1/(±1 + x(n)), n ∈ N_0. The form of solution of this equation, however, was first obtained in [10] but through induction principle. Then, with the solution of the above equation at hand, we prove a case ...

متن کامل

A new proof for the Banach-Zarecki theorem: A light on integrability and continuity

To demonstrate more visibly the close relation between thecontinuity and integrability, a new proof for the Banach-Zareckitheorem is presented on the basis of the Radon-Nikodym theoremwhich emphasizes on measure-type properties of the Lebesgueintegral. The Banach-Zarecki theorem says that a real-valuedfunction $F$ is absolutely continuous on a finite closed intervalif and only if it is continuo...

متن کامل

Uniqueness of Representation by Trigonometric Series

In 1870 Georg Cantor proved that a 2sr periodic omplex valued function of a real variable coincides with the values of at most one trigonometric series. We present his proof and then survey some of the many one dimensional generalizations and extensions of Cantor's theorem. We also survey the situation in higher dimensions, where a great deal less is known. 1. Cantor's uniqueness theorem. In 18...

متن کامل

Another proof of Banaschewski's surjection theorem

We present a new proof of Banaschewski's theorem stating that the completion lift of a uniform surjection is a surjection. The new procedure allows to extend the fact (and, similarly, the related theorem on closed uniform sublocales of complete uniform frames) to quasi-uniformities ("not necessarily symmetric uniformities"). Further, we show how a (regular) Cauchy point on a closed uniform subl...

متن کامل

ذخیره در منابع من


  با ذخیره ی این منبع در منابع من، دسترسی به آن را برای استفاده های بعدی آسان تر کنید

برای دانلود متن کامل این مقاله و بیش از 32 میلیون مقاله دیگر ابتدا ثبت نام کنید

ثبت نام

اگر عضو سایت هستید لطفا وارد حساب کاربری خود شوید

عنوان ژورنال:
  • The American Mathematical Monthly

دوره 117  شماره 

صفحات  -

تاریخ انتشار 2010